Kant’s Aesthetics
(Part 2)
b. The Deduction of Taste
There are two aspects to Kant’s basic answer to the
question of how aesthetic judgments happen. First, some of Kant’s earlier work
seemed to suggest that our faculty or ability to judge consisted of being a
mere processor of other, much more fundamental mental presentations. These were
concepts and intuitions (‘intuition’ being Kant’s word for our immediate
sensible experiences). Everything interesting and fundamental happened in the
formation of concepts, or in the receiving of intuitions. But now Kant argues
that judgment itself, as a faculty, has an fundamental principle that governs
it. This principle asserts the purposiveness of all phenomena with respect to
our judgment. In other words, it assumes in advance that everything we
experience can be tackled by our powers of judgment. Normally, we don’t even
notice that this assumption is being made, we just apply concepts, and be done
with it. But in the case of the beautiful, we do notice. This is because the
beautiful draws particular attention to its purposiveness; but also because the
beautiful has no concept of a purpose available, so that we cannot just apply a
concept and be done with it. Instead, the beautiful forces us to grope for
concepts that we can never find. And yet, nevertheless, the beautiful is not an
alien and disturbing experience – on the contrary, it is pleasurable. The
principle of purposiveness is satisfied, but in a new and unique way.
Asking what this new and unique way is takes us to the
second aspect. Kant argues that the kinds of ‘cognition’ (i.e. thinking)
characteristic of the contemplation of the beautiful are not, in fact, all that
different from ordinary cognition about things in the world. The faculties of
the mind are the same: the ‘understanding’ which is responsible for concepts,
and the ‘sensibility’ (including our imagination) which is responsible for
intuitions. The difference between ordinary and aesthetic cognition is that in
the latter case, there is no one ‘determinate’ concept that pins down an
intuition. Instead, intuition is allowed some ‘free play’, and rather than
being subject to one concept, it instead acts in ‘harmony’ with the lawfulness in
general of the understanding. It is this ability of judgment to bring
sensibility and understanding to a mutually reinforcing harmony that Kant calls
‘common sense’. This account of common sense explains how the beautiful can be
purposive with respect to our ability to judge, and yet have no definite
purpose. Kant believes common sense also answers the question of why aesthetic
judgments are valid: since aesthetic judgments are a perfectly normal function
of the same faculties of cognition involved in ordinary cognition, they will
have the same universal validity as such ordinary acts of cognition.
The idea of a harmony between or among the faculties of
cognition is turning out to be the key idea. For such a harmony, Kant claims,
will be purposive, but without purpose. Moreover, it will be both universal and
necessary, because based upon universal common sense, or again, because related
to the same cognitive faculties which enable any and all knowledge and
experience. Lastly, because of the self-contained nature of this harmony, it
must be disinterested. So, what does Kant think is going on in such ‘harmony’,
or in common sense for that matter, and does he have any arguments which make
of these idea more than mere metaphors for beauty?
Up to now, we have had no decent argument for the
existence of common sense as a principle of taste. At best, common sense was
plausible as a possible explanation of, for example, the tendency to
universality observed in aesthetic judgments. (As Kant admits in sect. 17).
Such a demand for universality could be accounted for nicely if we assumed an a
priori principle for taste, which might also explain the idea of universal
communicability. This argument, however, is rather weak. Kant believes he has
an ingenious route to proving the case with much greater certainty.
Throughout the Four Moments of the Beautiful, Kant has
dropped many important clues as to the transcendental account of the
possibility of aesthetic judgment: in particular, we have talked about
communicability, common sense and the harmony of the cognitive sub-faculties.
Kant then cuts off to turn to the sublime, representing a different problem
within aesthetic judgment. He returns to beauty in sect. 30, which forms the
transition to the passages tantalizingly called the Deduction. These
transitional passages feel much like a continuation of the Four Moments; we
will treat them as such here, since also Kant claims that the sublime does not
need a Deduction.
The Deduction in fact appears in two versions in Kant’s
texts (sect. 9 and 21 being the first; sect. 30-40 the second, with further
important clarification in the ‘Dialectic’ sect. 55-58). Here, we will discuss
only the second. Both explicitly are attempting to demonstrate the universal
communicability and thus intersubjective validity of judgments of taste. Which
for Kant is the same as saying that there is a ‘common sense’ – by which he
means that humans all must have a kind of sensing ability which operates the
same way.
Briefly, the argument begins by asserting that aesthetic
judgments must be judgments in some sense; that is, they are mental acts which
bring a sensible particular under some universal (Kant’s Introduction, IV). The
four moments of the beautiful are then explicitly seen as being limitations on
the conditions under which this judgment can take place (no interest, purposive
without determining purpose, etc.); all these Kant summarizes by saying that
the judgments are formal only, lacking all ‘matter’. By this, he means that
although the judgment is a judgment of the presentation of a particular
(singular) object, no particular determination of either sensible intuition, or
understanding forms a necessary part of the judgment. (In ordinary
cognition of the world, this lack of restriction would be entirely out of
place. It would be nonsense to judge whether a particular thing was a sofa
without restricting my judgment to that particular thing, and to the concept of
a sofa.) However, considered in general (that is, in their essence as
sub-faculties) the faculties of imagination and understanding are likewise
not restricted to any presentation or kind of sense, or any concept. This means
that Kant is describing the ‘proportion’ between understanding and intuition as
something like the always present possibility of the faculties being freed to
mutually enact their essence.
Because such faculties in general are required for all theoretical
cognition whatsoever, regardless of its object (as Kant claims to have proven
in the first Critique), they can be assumed present a priori, in the
same form and in the same way, in all human beings. The presence of the
cognitive sub-faculties in their various relations is equivalent with the
principle of the universal communicability and validity (i.e. common sense) of
any mental states in which these faculties are involved a priori. Therefore, an
aesthetic judgment must be seen to be an expression of this principle. The key
move is obviously to claim that the aesthetic judgment rests upon the same unique
conditions as ordinary cognition, and thus that the former must have the
same universal communicability and validity as the latter. It is just that,
presented with the beautiful, our cognitive faculties are released from the
limitations that characterize ordinary thought, and produce what above we
called a cascade of thoughts and feelings.
It is difficult to know what to make of this argument
(with the various other versions of it scattered throughout the text) and the
hypothesis it purports to prove. For one thing, Kant’s work here is so heavily
reliant upon the results of the first Critique as to not really be able
to stand on its own, while at the same time it is not clear at several points
whether the first and third Critiques are fully compatible. For another,
does not all this talk about the faculties ‘in general’ seem as if Kant is
hypostatising these faculties, as really existent things in the mind that act,
rather than simply as an expression for certain capacities? However, there is
no doubting the fascinating and profound implications of what Kant is
proposing. For example, the notions of common sense and communicability are
closely akin to key political ideas, leading several commentators to
propose that what Kant is really writing about are the foundations of any just
politics (see e.g. sect. 60). Or again, the ‘freedom’ of the imagination is
explicitly linked by Kant to the freedom characteristic of the moral will,
allowing Kant to construct a deeply rooted link between beauty and the moral
(sect. 59).
c. The Sublime
For Kant, the other basic type of aesthetic experience is
the sublime. The sublime names experiences like violent storms or huge
buildings which seem to overwhelm us; that is, we feel we ‘cannot get our head
around them’. This is either mainly ‘mathematical’ – if our ability to intuit
is overwhelmed by size (the huge building) – or ‘dynamical’ – if our ability to
will or resist is overwhelmed by force (e.g. the storm). The problem for Kant
here is that this experience seems to directly contradict the principle of the
purposiveness of nature for our judgment. And yet, Kant notes, one would expect
the feeling of being overwhelmed to also be accompanied by a feeling of fear or
at least discomfort. Whereas, the sublime can be a pleasurable experience. All
this raises the question of what is going on in the sublime.
Kant’s solution is that, in fact, the storm or the
building is not the real object of the sublime at all. Instead, what is
properly sublime are ideas of reason: namely, the ideas of absolute totality or
absolute freedom. However huge the building, we know it is puny compared to
absolute totality; however powerful the storm, it is nothing compared to
absolute freedom. The sublime feeling is therefore a kind of ‘rapid
alternation’ between the fear of the overwhelming and the peculiar pleasure of
seeing that overwhelming overwhelmed. Thus, it turns out that the sublime experience
is purposive after all – that we can, in some way, ‘get our head around it’.
Since the ideas of reason (particularly freedom) are also
important for Kant’s moral theory, there seems to be an interesting connection
between the sublime and morality. This Kant discusses under the heading of
‘moral culture’, arguing for example that the whole sublime experience would
not be possible if humans had not received a moral training that taught them to
recognize the importance of their own faculty of reason.
Traditionally, the sublime has been the name for objects
inspiring awe, because of the magnitude of their size/height/depth (e.g. the
ocean, the pyramids of Cheops), force (a storm), or transcendence (our idea of
God). Vis-à-vis the beautiful, the sublime presents some unique puzzles
to Kant. Three in particular are of note. First, that while the beautiful is
concerned with form, the sublime may even be (or even especially be)
formless. Second, that while the beautiful indicates (at least for judgment) a
purposiveness of nature that may have profound implications, the sublime
appears to be ‘counter-purposive’. That is, the object appears ill-matched to,
does ‘violence’ to, our faculties of sense and cognition. Finally, although
from the above one might expect the sublime experience to be painful in some
way, in fact the sublime does still involve pleasure – the question is ‘how?’.
Kant divides the sublime into the ‘mathematical’
(concerned with things that have a great magnitude in and of themselves) and
the ‘dynamically’ (things that have a magnitude of force in relation to
us, particularly our will). The mathematical sublime is defined as something ‘absolutely
large’ that is, ‘large beyond all comparison’ (sect. 25). Usually,
we apply some kind of standard of comparison, although this need not be
explicit (e.g. ‘Mt. Blanc is large’ usually means ‘compared with other
mountains (or perhaps, with more familiar objects), Mt. Blanc is large’). The
absolutely large, however, is not the result of a comparison.
Now, of course, any object is measurable – even the size
of the universe, no less a mountain on Earth. But Kant then argues that
measurement not merely mathematical in nature (the counting of units), but
fundamentally relies upon the ‘aesthetic’ (in the sense of ‘intuitive’ as used
in the first Critique) grasp of a unit of measure. Dealing with a unit
of measure, whether it be a millimeter or a kilometer, requires a number (how
many units) but also a sense of what the unit is. This means that there will be
absolute limits on properly aesthetic measurement because of the limitations of
the finite, human faculties of sensibility. In the first place, there must be
an absolute unit of measure, such that nothing larger could be ‘apprehended’;
in the second place, there must be a limit to the number of such units that can
be held together in the imagination and thus ‘comprehended’ (sect. 26). An
object that exceeds these limits (regardless of its mathematical size) will be
presented as absolutely large – although of course it is still so with
respect to our faculties of sense.
However, we must return to the second and third peculiar
puzzles of the sublime. As we saw above with respect to the beautiful, pleasure
lies in the achievement of a purpose, or at least in the recognition of a
purposiveness. So, if the sublime presents itself as counter-purposive, why and
how is pleasure associated with it? In other words, where is the purposiveness
of the sublime experience? Kant writes,
[W]e express ourselves entirely incorrectly when we call
this or that object of nature sublime … for how can we call something by a term
of approval if we apprehend it as in itself contrapurposive? (sect. 23)
This problem constitutes Kant’s principle argument that
something else must be going on in the sublime experience other than the mere
overwhelmingness of some object. As Kant will later claim, objects of sense
(oceans, pyramids, etc.) are called ‘sublime’ only by a kind of covert
sleight-of-hand, what he calls a ‘subreption’ (sect. 27). In fact, what is
actually sublime, Kant argues, are ideas of our own reason. The
overwhelmingness of sensible objects leads the minds to these ideas.
Now, such presentations of reason are necessarily
unexhibitable by sense. Moreover, the faculty of reason is not merely an inert
source of such ideas, but characteristically demands that its ideas be
presented. (This same demand is what creates all the dialectical problems that
Kant analyses in, for example, the Antinomies.) Kant claims that the relation
of the overwhelming sensible object to our sense is in a kind of ‘harmony’
(sect. 27) or analogy to the relation of the rational idea of absolute
totality to any sensible object or faculty. The sublime experience, then,
is a two-layer process. First, a contrapurposive layer in which our faculties
of sense fail to complete their task of presentation. Second, a strangely
purposive layer in which this very failure constitutes a ‘negative exhibition’
(‘General Comment’ following sect. 29) of the ideas of reason (which could not
otherwise be presented). This ‘exhibition’ thus also provides a purposiveness
of the natural object for the fulfillment of the demands of reason. Moreover,
and importantly, it also provides a new and ‘higher’ purposiveness to the
faculties of sense themselves which are now understood to be properly
positioned with respect to our ‘supersensible vocation’ (sect. 27) – i.e. in
the ultimately moral hierarchy of the faculties. Beyond simply comprehending
individual sensible things, our faculty of sensibility, we might say, now knows
what it is for. We will return to this point shortly. The consequence of
this purposiveness is exactly that ‘negative pleasure’ (sect. 23) for which we
had be searching. The initial displeasure of the ‘violence’ against our apparent
sensible interests is now matched by a ‘higher’ pleasure arising from the
strange purposiveness Kant has discovered. Interestingly, on Kant’s
description, neither of these feelings wins out – instead, the sublime feeling
consists of a unique ‘vibration’ or ‘rapid alternation’ of these feelings
(sect. 27).
The dynamically sublime is similar. In this case, a
‘might’ or power is observed in nature that is irresistible with respect to our
bodily or sensible selves. Such an object is ‘fearful’ to be sure, but (because
we remain disinterested) is not an object of fear. (Importantly, one of Kant’s
examples here is religion: God is fearful but the righteous man is not afraid.
This is the difference, he says, between a rational religion and mere
superstition.) Again, the sublime is a two-layered experience. Kant writes that
such objects ‘raise the soul’s fortitude above its usual middle range and allow
us to discover in ourselves an ability to resist which is of a quite different
kind…’ (sect. 28). In particular, nature is called ‘sublime merely because it
elevates the imagination to the exhibition of those cases wherein the mind can
be made to feel [sich fühlbar machen] the sublimity, even above nature,
that is proper to its vocation’ (sect. 28, translation modified). In
particular, the sublimity belongs to human freedom which is (by
definition) unassailable to the forces of nature. Such a conception of freedom
as being outside the order of nature, but demanding action upon that order, is
the core of Kant’s moral theory. Thus we can begin to see the intimate
connection between the sublime (especially here the dynamically sublime) and
morality.
This connection (for the sublime in general) becomes even
more explicit in Kant’s discussion of what he calls ‘moral culture’. (sect. 29)
The context is to ask about the modality of judgments on the sublime – that is,
to they have the same implicit demand on the necessary assent of others that
judgments on the beautiful have? Kant’s answer is complicated. There is an
empirical factor which is required for the sublime: the mind of the experiencer
must be ‘receptive’ to rational ideas, and this can only happen in a culture
that already understands morality as being a function of freedom or,
more generally, conceives of human beings as having a dimension which in some
way transcends nature. The sublime, properly speaking, is possible only for
members of such a moral culture (and, Kant sometimes suggests, may reciprocally
contribute to the strengthening of that culture). So, the sublime is subjected
to an empirical contingency. However, Kant claims, we are justified in
demanding from everyone that they necessarily have the transcendental
conditions for such moral culture, and thus for the sublime, because these
conditions are (as in the case of the beautiful) the same as for theoretical
and practical thought in general. The claims about moral culture show that, for
Kant, aesthetics in general is not an isolated problem for philosophy but
intimately linked to metaphysical and moral questions. This is one more reason
why it is important not to assume that the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment
is a book merely about beauty and sublimity. Moreover, this ‘link’ has
an even greater significance for Kant: it shows reflective judgment in action
as it were relating together both theoretical and practical reason, for this
was the grand problem he raised in his Introduction.
Kant’s treatment of the sublime raises many difficulties.
For example, only the dynamically sublime has any strict relationship to the
moral idea of freedom. This raises the question of whether the mathematical and
dynamically sublime are in fact radically different, both in themselves as
experiences, and in their relation to ‘moral culture’. Again, Kant gives an
interesting account of how magnitude is estimated in discussing the
mathematical sublime, but skips the parallel problem in the dynamically sublime
(how does one estimate force?). Finally, many readers have found the premise of
the whole discussion implausible: that in the sublime experience, what is
properly sublime and the object of respect should be the idea of reason, rather
than nature.
d. Fine Art and Genius
Thus far, Kant’s main focus for the discussion of beauty
and the sublime has been nature. He now turns to fine art. Kant assumes that
the cognition involved in judging fine art is similar to the cognition involved
in judging natural beauty. Accordingly, the problem that is new to fine art is
not how it is judged by a viewer, but how it is created. The solution revolves
around two new concepts: the ‘genius’ and ‘aesthetic ideas’.
Kant argues that art can be tasteful (that is, agree with
aesthetic judgment) and yet be ‘soulless’ – lacking that certain something that
would make it more than just an artificial version of a beautiful natural
object. What provides soul in fine art is an aesthetic idea. An aesthetic idea
is a counterpart to a rational idea: where the latter is a concept that could
never adequately be exhibited sensibly, the former is a set of sensible
presentations to which no concept is adequate. An aesthetic idea, then, is as
successful an attempt as possible to ‘exhibit’ the rational idea. It is the
talent of genius to generate aesthetic ideas, but that is not all. First, the
mode of expression must also be tasteful – for the understanding’s ‘lawfulness’
is the condition of the expression being in any sense universal and capable of
being shared. The genius must also find a mode of expression which allows a
viewer not just to ‘understand’ the work conceptually, but to reach something
like the same excited yet harmonious state of mind that the genius had in
creating.
Starting in sect. 43, Kant addresses himself particularly
to fine art for the first time. The notion of aesthetic judgment already
developed remains central. But unlike the investigation of beauty in nature,
the focus shifts from the transcendental conditions for judgment of the
beautiful object to the transcendental conditions of the making of fine art. In
other words: how is it possible to make art? To solve this, Kant will introduce
the notion of genius.
But that is not the only shift. Kant stands right in the
middle of a complete historical change in the central focus of aesthetics.
While formerly, philosophical aesthetics was largely content to take its
primary examples of beauty and sublimity from nature, after Kant the focus is
placed squarely on works of art. Now, in Kant, fine art seems to ‘borrow’ its
beauty or sublimity from nature. Fine art is therefore a secondary concept. On
the other hand, of course, in being judged aesthetically, nature is seen ‘as
if’ purposeful, designed, or a product of an intelligence. So, in this case at
least, the notion of ‘nature’ itself can be seen as secondary with respect to
the notions of design or production, borrowed directly from art. Thus, the
relation between nature and art is much more complex than it seems at first.
Kant’s work thus forms an important part of the historical change mentioned
above. Moreover, it is clear from a number of comments that Kant makes about
‘genius’ that he is an aesthetic conservative reacting against, for example,
the emphasis on the individual, impassioned artist characteristic of the ‘Sturm
und Drang’ movement. But, historically, his discussion of the concept
contributed to the escalation of the concept in the early 19th Century.
So, in order to understand how art is possible, we have
to first understand what art is, and what art production is, vis-á-vis
natural objects and natural ‘production’. First, then, what does Kant mean by
‘nature’? (1) On the one hand, in expressions like ‘the nature of X’ (e.g. ‘the
nature of human cognition’), it means those properties which belong essentially
to X. This can either be an empirical claim or, more commonly in Kant, a
priori. On the other hand, nature as itself an object has several meanings for
Kant. Especially: (2) If I say ‘nature as opposed to art’ I mean that realm of
objects not presented as the objects of sensible will – that is, which are
quite simply not made or influenced by human hands. (3) If I say ‘nature as an
object of cognition’ I mean any object capable of being dealt with
‘objectively’ or ‘scientifically’. This includes things in space outside of us,
but also aspects of sensible human nature that are the objects of sciences such
as psychology. (4) Nature is also the object of reflective judgments and is
that which is presupposed to be purposive or pre-adapted with respect to
judgment.
Kant begins by giving a long clarification of art. As a
general term, again, art refers to the activity of making according to a
preceding notion. If I make a chair, I must know, in advance, what a chair
is. We distinguish art from nature because (though we may judge nature
purposive) we know in fact there is no prior notion behind the activity of a
flower opening. The flower doesn’t have an idea of opening prior to opening –
the flower doesn’t have a mind or a will to have or execute ideas with.
Art also means something different from science – as Kant
says, it is a skill distinguished from a type of knowledge. Art
involves some kind of practical ability, irreducible to determinate concepts,
which is distinct from a mere comprehension of something. The latter can be
fully taught; the former, although subject to training to be sure, relies upon
native talent. (Thus, Kant will later claim, there can be no such thing as a
scientific genius, because a scientific mind can never be radically
original. See sect. 46.) Further, art is distinguished from labor or craft
- the latter being something satisfying only for the payoff which results and
not for the mere activity of making itself. Art (not surprisingly, like beauty)
is free from any interest in the existence of the product itself.
contd…
No comments:
Post a Comment