Welcome!!!

Books for ever. . . . .

Monday, May 28, 2012

Literary Theory and Criticism, Part-VIII


Poststructuralism

The Essence of Poststructuralism

The name says everything and nothing. It comes after structuralism; it is a reaction against structuralism. But, in its critique of structuralism, it was not conducting a postmortem. Structuralist influence continued to be very much alive and kicking. It was also a very complex phenomenon, which cannot be explained just by its relationship to structuralism. It must also be stressed that poststructuralism and deconstruction theory are parts of a continuum and that it is mainly for the sake of clarity that they have been allotted separate sections. Many of the theorists too are relevant, not only to poststructuralism and deconstruction theory, but also to psychoanalysis and feminism. Names such as Jacques Lacan, Paul de Man, Hélène Cixous, Julia Kristeva and others will recur. However, examining what poststructuralism found to be wrong with structuralism is as good a place to start as any. The great guru of the structuralists, Saussure,was about to be dethroned, because a signifier was no longer perceived as signifying anything any more. Or not quite as Saussure envisaged it, at least.
With every ‘sign’, Saussure had posited, ‘signifier’ and  ‘signified’ were two sides of the same coin. Although they were in an arbitrary relationship, they stuck together through thick and thin. The word ‘dog’ and that furry creature there wagging its tail were permanently wed (at least, in the English language they were).Then poststructuralism came along and threw doubt on this whole cosy little arrangement. For them a ‘sign’ is a very temporary coming together of ‘signifier’ and ‘signified’: a one-night stand. The very dictionary itself, the fount of all certainty about language, proves the point. When you seek the meaning of a word in a dictionary you are indefinitely deferred. Look up that word ‘dog’ and you find ‘a common four-legged animal, especially any of the many varieties kept by humans…’ etc. Look up ‘animal’ and you find ‘a living creature, not a plant.’ Look up ‘living creature’… and so on ad infinitum. For poststructuralists, signifiers form complex patterns of meaning with other signifiers and their meanings can never be pinned down. Many of these ideas are expounded in full by Jacques Derrida but, as he is closely associated with the concept of ‘deconstruction’, his ideas will be examined in that section.
Saussure’s concepts of ‘parole’ (language as utterance) and ‘langue’ (language competence) were also under attack by the poststructuralists. Structuralists were interested primarily in ‘langue’, the deep structure which makes communication and meaning possible. But poststructuralists saw ‘langue’ as a kind of myth. Language does not have an impersonal structure underlying utterances. It is always and only an articulated system, which interacts with other systems of meaning and with human social existence. This concept of language poststructuralists prefer to call ‘discourse’.
According to poststructuralists everything is discourse. Objective reporting of things and events in language is simply impossible. All language, meaning everything we can potentially say, pre-exists our utilisation of it. Subject and object cannot be sharply distinguished. This not only applies to our use of language but to all systems of knowledge, including science. New knowledge is attained when there is a jump from one accepted form of discourse to a completely new one, a paradigm-shift.
This blurring of the distinctions between subject and object also throws the whole notion of personal identity into doubt. When I use the pronoun ‘I’ or refer to myself as ‘me’, these are also signifiers which are unstable. It implies that ‘I’ can never be fully present to ‘you’, and consequently ‘you’ can never be fully present to ‘me’. The notion of a stable, unified self is a fiction. Another interesting aspect of this is that, according to poststructuralists, when we speak we have a greater sense of being at one with the ‘I’ who speaks, than we do, when writing, with the ‘I’ who writes. Writing is second-hand, at one remove from consciousness. It is alienated from the self. This is why the identity of the ‘I’ in writing is always suspect. However, one should be cautious of granting this belief universal validity, as there are people who claim to be more at one with their self when writing than when speaking.

Roland Barthes (1915–1980)

A central tenet of Barthes’ thought is that all forms of communication and representation are conventional. He despises the writer who deludes him/herself and his or her readers into thinking that language can be a transparent medium, through which it is possible to transmit clear unambiguous ideas or images of reality. A writer should be honest about the artificiality of what he or she is doing.
Something which characterises much poststructuralist thought is the occurrence of infinite regress or doubt. In Elements of Semiology (1967), Barthes expresses the belief that structuralism can be applied to all sign systems. However, he thinks that, by the same token, structuralism can also be subjected to a structural analysis, and indeed to other modes of analysis. Following upon this he cannot avoid the conclusion that metalanguages (processes of thought that reflect on other modes of thought or processes) can be subject themselves to analysis by other metalanguages ad infinitum. All forms of thought are by this token, therefore, fictions. No ultimate truth is ever discernible.
The most famous of Barthes’ works is, undoubtedly, The Death of the Author (1968). In this essay, he rejects the view that an author is the originator of his text and the sole authority for its valid interpretation. A work in no way and on no level reflects an author’s intentions concerning the work. The author is nothing more than the location where a verbal event takes place. The reader can therefore approach the text from any direction whatsoever, and can interpret the text (the ‘signifier’) without respecting any intended meaning (the ‘signified’).
In The Pleasure of the Text (1975), Barthes pursues this self-indulgence on the part of the reader even further. For him, there are two kinds of pleasure to be gained in reading a text. The first is simple ‘pleasure’. We feel this when we perceive something more than the simple and obvious meaning of what we read. We make an association, draw an inference, recall an image etc. This disrupts the linear flow of the text. Something, in a sense unjustified, is brought into association with the basic meanings of a text. We gain pleasure also from the rhythm of the narrative and from allowing our attention to wander. All this is acceptable and non-provocative in the context of normal cultural pursuits.
Barthes’ second type of pleasure is what must appear to be an odd interpretation of the concept for most people. For many it is difficult to identify it as a kind of pleasure at all. The word he uses for it is jouissance, which means ‘pleasure’ in French, but which is usually translated as ‘bliss’, as he clearly envisages a stronger, virtually orgasmic form of pleasure. For Barthes, it is clearly something akin to the thrill of revolutionary feelings or actions. A text which provides a sense of ‘bliss’ ‘unsettles the reader’s historical, cultural, psychological assumptions’. It is the thrill of discovering the new, the dangerous, that which threatens chaos, anarchy. If the reader is not receptive to such an experience, he or she will feel only boredom but surrendering to it will bring the sense of ‘bliss’. It seems a little like the effect which Franz Kafka required of a good book: that of an ice-axe breaking the frozen sea of the mind.
One of Barthes’ most notorious books, which many consider to be his most impressive, is the oddly named S/Z (1970). In this work he starts with a thorough critique of structuralist attempts to trace common basic structures in all stories. He is more interested in what makes them different than what they have common. Every text refers back, in different ways, to all other texts that have ever been written. For Barthes, there are two types of text: that which allows the reader only to comprehend in a predetermined way and that which makes the reader into the producer of his or her own meaning. The first type of text he calls ‘readerly’ (lisible) and the other ‘writerly’ (scriptible). It is clear that Barthes prefers the second kind: ‘this ideal text is a galaxy of signifiers, not a structure of signifieds.’ It is possible for a reader to apply an infinite number of interpretations to such a text. None of them needs to be compatible nor part of an overall unity.
Barthes demonstrates his approach to actual texts by breaking down a novella by Honoré de Balzac (Sarrasine) according to specific codes. He first divides the story into a random number of reading units (581 ‘lexias’). Each of them is then subjected to analysis according to five codes:
1. Hermeneutic (relating to the enigma or mystery in the story).
2. Semic (relating to associations evoked).
3. Symbolic (relating to polarities and antitheses in the story).
4. Proairetic (relating to basic action and behaviour).
5. Cultural (relating to commonly shared cultural knowledge between text and reader).
The Balzac story is commonly regarded as a realist work and Barthes, in Terry Eagleton’s words, ‘drastically rewrites and reorganizes it out of all conventional recognition’. Sarrasine thereby becomes what Barthes terms a ‘limit text’ for literary realism. His analysis reveals the limits of the realist mode of writing.

Michel Foucault (1926–1984)

The post that Michel Foucault held at the Collège de France, Paris, at the time of his death, aptly sums up his unique specialist field: ‘Professor of the History of Systems of Thought’. He can justifiably be described as poststructuralist in one important sense. The structuralists used  linguistics as their model of analysis but Foucault considered this inadequate and focused instead on the history of social and political systems and discourses. Because of this, he has been very influential in the field of literary history. His concept of ‘discourse’ needs some clarification.
Foucault’s use of the term ‘discourse’ is closely related to his concept of power. The power of the human sciences (eg psychology, economics etc) derives from their claims to be knowledge. They expect respect for their claims and thereby exert power and influence. Practitioners in these fields set themselves up as experts and it is through their claimed expertise that power is exerted. For Foucault, a discourse is a loose structure of interconnected assumptions which makes knowledge possible. He expounded this idea most clearly in his work The Archaeology of Knowledge (1972), in which he asserted that discourse can be defined as a large group of statements belonging to a single system of formation, what he calls a ‘discursive formation’. He cites the examples of ‘clinical discourse, economic discourse, the discourse of natural history, psychiatric discourse’. One of the main reasons why knowledge can be a form of power is that it is a method of defining and categorising other people. It leads eventually to disciplining those who do not conform or, in the case of psychiatry, those who are defined as unsocial or criminal. It also leads to surveillance, what Foucault calls ‘panopticism’. This is realised, for example, in the form of policing and the setting up guards in prisons to observe every move of the inmates. Of course, when considering the latter part of the twentieth century, one might want to add the advent of widespread CCTV surveillance.
Foucault was greatly influenced by the German philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche and his concept of power. Nietzsche argued that all forms of knowledge are expressions of the ‘Will to Power’. On this assumption it is not possible to assume the existence of absolute truths or any kind of objective knowledge. An idea or theory is only ‘true’ if it accords with notions of truth held by the prevailing authorities of the day, whether intellectual or political. For Foucault, what it is possible for an author to say changes from one period to another. What is considered normal or rational in any given period is confirmed by rules, tacit or otherwise. Those who do not abide by the rules are excluded from the prevailing discourse, and are either suppressed or condemned as mad. The education system is also important in institutionalising these  rules and inculcating them into the minds of new generations.
Foucault points out that different forms of knowledge have arisen in different historical periods and been replaced eventually by new systems of thought. For him, history is such a series of disconnected discursive practices. Specifically he was interested in the fields of psychiatry, medicine, sex and crime. It must be stressed that the rules governing such discourses are not consciously employed. We can understand the bodies of discourse of earlier eras only because we are governed by different discourses and are remote from that era. As we view past discourses through our own unconscious discourses, we can never possess an objective knowledge of history.
The work of Foucault which deals most explicitly with writing and authorship is the essay What is an Author? (1969). In this essay, he recognises the importance of Barthes’ essay The Death of the Author but views the question of authorship as being more complex. However, the idea of an ideal society in which literature could circulate anonymously appeals to him greatly. It would seem that, for Foucault, the aim of writing is not to express the self or to fix a meaning but to create an individual object behind which the writer can efface him or herself: ‘Writing unfolds like a game that invariably goes beyond its own rules and transgresses its limits. In writing, the point is not to manifest or exalt the act of writing, nor is it to pin a subject within language; it is rather a question of creating a space into which the writing subject constantly disappears.’
In one sense, Foucault does consider the author to be dead, but this death is one in which the author is complicit. The author of fiction especially attempts to deny his or her presence (it would seem that Foucault is thinking of realist fiction in particular): ‘Using all the contrivances that he sets up between himself and what he writes, the writing subject cancels out the signs of his particular individuality. As a result, the mark of the writer is reduced to nothing more than the singularity of his absence; he must assume the role of the dead man in the game of writing.’

No comments:

Post a Comment